Law in Contemporary Society

View   r4  >  r3  >  r2  >  r1
MarcLegrandFirstPaper 4 - 29 Apr 2012 - Main.MarcLegrand
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="FirstPaper"
Changed:
<
<

Perry v. Brown v. Cohen

>
>

Suspect Classes

 

Introduction

Deleted:
<
<
I wanted to write about the recently-decided Ninth Circuit opinion in Perry v. Brown, and I thought it might be interesting (at least for me) to try to apply a few of the ideas from Felix Cohen’s Transcendental Nonsense.
 
Changed:
<
<

Legal Concepts

>
>
In light of Perry v. Brown and the handful of DOMA challenges pending in various stages of court, it’s pertinent to consider the level of scrutiny applied to government discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation. Courts will also consider whether various framings of a "right to marry" are "fundamental", but that’s not my focus.
 
Changed:
<
<
"Legal concepts … are supernatural entities which do not have a verifiably existence except to the eyes of faith." (Cohen, 821).
>
>

Defining Suspect Classes

 
Changed:
<
<
The Perry majority frames the question they have been asked to decide as follows:
>
>
The characteristics of suspect classes
 
Changed:
<
<
"[Did] the People of California have legitimate reasons for enacting a constitutional amendment that serves only to take away from same-sex couples the right to have their lifelong relationships dignified by the official status of 'marriage,' and to compel the State ...to substitute the label of 'domestic partnership' for their relationships?" (1615).
>
>
In Carolene Products, Justice Stone suggested that “statutes directed at particular religious, national, or racial minorities” and “prejudice against discrete and insular minorities” could warrant “more searching judicial inquiry.”
 
Changed:
<
<
In this framing, the crucial word seems to be "legitimate." When Cohen describes a court's approach to determining "actual value," he points out that "[t]he actual value of a utility's property, then, is a function of the court's decision, and the court's decision cannot be based in fact upon the actual value of the property." (Cohen, 818). The idea of "legitimacy" in Perry v. Brown is a similarly circular legal conclusion; whether or not there was a legitimate reason for enacting Proposition 8 is a function of whether or not the court finds that there was.
>
>
The Court has since provided various attempts at elaboration. Suspect classes face a “history of purposeful unequal treatment”(1) based on “an immutable characteristic determined solely by the accident of birth”(2) and is “so seldom relevant to the achievement of any legitimate state interest that laws grounded in such considerations are deemed to reflect prejudice and antipathy.”(3) They may also be “relegated to such a position of political powerlessness as to command extraordinary protection from the majoritarian political process.”(4)

Notes

1 , 4 : San Antonio v. Rodriguez

2 : Frontiero v. Richardson

3 : Cleburne v. Cleburne


 
Changed:
<
<
The dissenting judge frames his reasoning in equally self-referential terms, stating that he is "not convinced that Proposition 8 lacks a rational relationship to legitimate state interests." (1673). Here, the keyword "legitimate" is modified by equally unhelpful "state interests." The primary issue supporters of Proposition 8 identified as a "state interest" was that of procreation and childrearing. It's hard for me to see what about this topic is inherently part of a state's interest; the kinds of arguments that justify such a connection seem to me to justify almost any activity as a matter of "state interest." In any case, there is no extra-legal practical definition of "state interests," it is again a legal conclusion reached by courts when courts think it should be reached.
>
>
Which classes are/aren’t suspect
 
Changed:
<
<
Is the goal in these two grafs to forget any Fourteenth Amendment law you know, to avoid learning any, or to indicate that it is transcendental nonsense so that it doesn't matter whether you learn it or forget it?
>
>
The Court has been unwilling to expand the realm of suspect classification beyond those initially suggested three-quarters of a century ago (race, national origin, and religion). Two of the classifications find strong Constitutional support for suspect status. In the context of the 14th Amendment, race-based distinctions are obviously inherently suspect in equal protection jurisprudence. Suspicion towards religious classifications has a solid foundation in the 1st Amendment (and thus the 14th Amendment). National origin may have a weaker Constitutional basis for special protection, but likely reflects contemporary tensions resulting from the wave of immigration in the decades preceding Carolene Products.
 
Changed:
<
<
The dissent here mentions the "rational basis" test, the default level of scrutiny employed by courts in due process and equal protection cases. This raises another host of transcendental nonsense concerns. The first is the decision to apply rational basis review, rather than intermediate or strict scrutiny. "Proposition 8 is a classification neither involving fundamental rights nor proceeding along suspect lines . . . [so] I do not address the application of strict scrutiny review." (1651). Why isn't marriage a fundamental right, despite the fact that the Supreme Court stated that "[m]arriage is one of the basic civil rights of man, fundamental to our very existence and survival" while striking down anti-miscegenation statutes? Loving v. Virginia, 87 S.Ct. 1817, 1824 (1967).
>
>
Later cases have labeled sex(5), parental marital status(6), and parental legal immigration status(7) as quasi-suspect classifications subject to intermediate scrutiny.

Notes

5 : J.E.B. v. Alabama

6 : Clark v. Jeter

7 : Plyler v. Doe


 
Changed:
<
<
Why cite the case to the unofficial reporter? Because Westlaw prefers to take you away from the US Reports? Why don't you link directly to the opinion online, so people can read it? Did you? It would have answered the rhetorical question you asked, and given you some further basis to understand the legal analysis in the case you are supposedly trying to grasp.
>
>
Some classifications found not suspect include age(8), physical(9) and mental(10) disability, and poverty(11).

Notes

8 : Massachusetts v. Murgia

9 : Alabama v. Garrett


 
Changed:
<
<
Because the judge here says so. A suspect class is loosely defined as a minority group which has been purposefully discriminated against because of an immutable characteristic (religion is included, raising questions about the definition of immutability). Why are homosexuals not a suspect class? Because the judge here says so.
>
>

The classification of sexual orientation, actual and potential:

 
Changed:
<
<
Perhaps because the Supreme Court has not said so? You have neither reviewed the law concerning the definition of suspect classes nor explained why the Court of Appeals, well aware that the Supreme Court has declined repeated opportunities to rule on the question, should have done so.
>
>
What the Court has said
 
Added:
>
>
The only majority opinion to consider sexual orientation in an equal protection framework is Romer v. Evans. The Court applied rationality review, implicitly refusing to recognize orientation as a suspect classification.
 
Changed:
<
<
Even if the decision to choose "rational basis" review could be defended in real-world terms, we would not have advanced very far in our battle against transcendental nonsense. We would have to investigate more legal conclusions: whether or not Proposition 8 was "reasonably" related to, again, a "legitimate state interest."
>
>
Could sexual orientation be a suspect classification?
 
Changed:
<
<
Given that "marriage" itself is transcendental nonsense in the same sense you're using it here, what battle against transcendental nonsense could we be fighting? If you're really going to apply the approach you seem to think you're endorsing here, the case isn't about anything and doesn't have any meaning no matter which way it comes out.
>
>
Because of the Court’s longstanding refusal to expand the list of suspect classes, arguing that sexual orientation is a quasi-suspect class may be more productive. The uncertainty regarding what renders a class suspect versus quasi-suspect means most arguments in favor of one standard are largely applicable to the other.
 
Changed:
<
<

Words are what they do

>
>
Could sexual orientation be rendered a suspect classification by the challenged action?
 
Changed:
<
<
"[T]he meaning of a definition is found in its consequences." (Cohen, 838).
>
>
“[P]rejudice against discrete and insular minorities” may hinder “political processes ordinarily…relied upon to protect minorities.” Even if sexual orientation isn’t a suspect classification in a theoretical vacuum, state action that places a badge of inferiority on homosexuality arguably creates a suspect class.(12)

Notes

12 : Carolene Products; see Amicus brief by Karlan and Moglen in Romer


 
Changed:
<
<
I was reminded of the discussion regarding the PPACA and whether there is a meaningful difference between calling something a "penalty" or a "tax." In Perry v. Brown, even the majority recognized that those with "domestic partnerships" in California were entitled to "rights and responsibilities that are identical to those of married spouses . . . ." (1610). At first glance, this may seem like an analogy for the penalty/tax argument, a matter of mere semantics. However, the word "marriage" has a unique place in our society, and the majority included a 300-word paragraph detailing this fact (page 1613). You can read a short blog post that includes the relevant paragraph here.
>
>
Could sexual orientation be a quasi-suspect classification, based on the standards outlined above?
 
Changed:
<
<
If you need the quotation, why not point at it in the opinion? If you don't need it, why are you sending your reader to some random person's blog? Why did you need to cite another complex case you're going to discuss in order not to discuss the reasoning about why "marriage" isn't transcendental nonsense within the borders of an opinion you're dismissing on that ground anyway?
>
>
A history of purposeful unequal treatment
 
Changed:
<
<
Similarly, the supporters of Proposition 8 argued that there was no difference between the rights of homosexuals before In re Marriage Cases, 43 Cal.4th 757 (Cal 2008) and after Proposition 8 passed. Only in the intervening six month period were homosexuals able to marry in California. Not even the majority claims that states are constitutionally required to extend marriage to homosexual couples, and the supporters of Prop 8 argue that there is no difference between not extending the right to marry and revoking the right to marry. Just as the majority argued above that there is unique symbolism to the word "marriage," here they argued that there is symbolic importance to the act of revoking the right to marry. I agree that a state’s active revocation of a certain group’s rights puts an official stamp on discrimination.
>
>
The Rodriguez majority, including Justice Rehnquist, called this a “traditional indicia of suspectness.” This is curious because the opinions Rehnquist joined in Bowers, Romer, and Lawrence all cited longstanding discrimination against homosexuals as clear evidence that such treatment was within state power. I agree with early Rehnquist; a history of discrimination merits closer scrutiny to determine if the State is acting out of entrenched bias or legitimate concerns.
 
Changed:
<
<
In which case, why not go further and argue that doing so creates a suspect class where there was none before? See my brief with Pam Karlan in Romer v. Evans.
>
>
Political powerlessness [requiring] protection from the majoritarian political process
 
Changed:
<
<

Judges are people, too

>
>
Justice Brennan has argued that the “severe opprobrium often manifested against homosexuals once so identified publicly” rendered the group “particularly powerless to pursue their rights openly in the political arena.”(13) Justice Scalia in Romer called homosexuals a “politically powerful minority.” If homosexuality is considered deviant, then perhaps any move towards greater protection suggests political power. I disagree. Romer was decided in May 1996, three weeks after DOMA was introduced in the House. Homosexual sex was only decriminalized nationwide in 2003, and not through the political process. Today, only six states allow same-sex marriages. This suggests a minority that is more discrete and insular than politically powerful.

Notes

13 : The dissent to a denial of petition for writ of certiorari, joined by Justice Marshall, also endorsed defining homosexuals as a suspect class.


 
Changed:
<
<
"There is at present no publication showing the political, economic, and professional background and activities of our various judges." (Cohen, 846)
>
>
An immutable characteristic determined solely by the accident of birth
 
Changed:
<
<
Publication or not, we know that the majority was written by Judge Reinhardt and Judge Hawkins, nominated by Jimmy Carter and Bill Clinton, respectively. Judge Smith, who dissented, was nominated by George W. Bush. "According to the classical theory, these things have nothing to do with the way courts decide cases." (Cohen, 846). Even in a functionalist model, such facts are not necessarily determinative. After all, Proposition 8 was first struck down in district court by Judge Walker, who was originally nominated by Ronald Reagan and then re-nominated by George H. W. Bush. Still, the fact that the opinion in Perry v. Brown is basically premised on self-referential legal conclusions makes me wonder what role human biases played in the determination of those conclusions.
>
>
The rule may or may not apply to sexual orientation, but it’s problematic regardless. The Court’s reasoning that “legal burdens should bear some relationship to individual responsibility”(14) subtly endorses discrimination. If a group is truly equal, then questions of fault are misplaced.
 
Changed:
<
<
-- By MarcLegrand - 13 Feb 2012
>
>

Does the purported level of scrutiny even matter?

 
Added:
>
>
Is the Court being honest?
 
Changed:
<
<
I don't understand this draft. The use of Cohen seems to be primarily to make it unnecessary to understand the law you're trying to learn something about. You don't make it easier for the reader to understand the case, you distract yourself into making some minor errors or omissions of your own, and when it's over we don't seem to know anything about what happened that we didn't know before.
>
>
The Romer majority claimed to use rationality review, but rejected three state justifications for Amendment 2.(15) I’m happy with the decision, but it doesn’t follow the extremely deferential floor set in other cases: rationality review doesn’t delve into the “wisdom, fairness, or logic”(16) of proposed rationales, nor even require that the state “actually articulate at any time the purpose or rationale supporting its classification.”(17) It’s hard to determine the difference between Romer’s rational basis “with bite” and intermediate scrutiny; would any justices change their decision in any case based on the other standard being applied?

Notes

15 : Preserving resources to combat more traditional discrimination, preserving freedom of association, and achieving statewide uniformity in civil rights laws.

16 : F.C.C. v. Beach Communications

17 : Nordlinger v. Hahn


 
Changed:
<
<
Why not try another draft that presents an idea of yours about the opinions, and which also involves actually explaining what legal issues the court thinks it's deciding and how it decides them?
>
>
What is a rational basis for discrimination?
 
Changed:
<
<
>
>
So seldom relevant to the achievement of any legitimate state interest that laws grounded in such considerations are deemed to reflect prejudice and antipathy.

This is another standard used to define a suspect class, but I put it here because it’s the heart of the issue. When is sexual orientation relevant to a legitimate state interest? The only practical difference between heterosexuals and others relates to procreation and carries significant caveats.(18) This seems to implicate few, if any, legitimate state interests. State power shouldn’t be wielded at the moral whim of the majority to discriminate against disapproved groups.

I see no principled reason to deny sexual orientation quasi-suspect status, but I'm unsure how important the distinction is. I find it hard to imagine any standard but the most toothless rationality review that would uphold government discrimination based on orientation.

Notes

18 : Not all heterosexuals can procreate, and not all that can do. Most non-heterosexuals could, if they chose to. Both can raise adopted children.



MarcLegrandFirstPaper 3 - 15 Apr 2012 - Main.EbenMoglen
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="FirstPaper"
Line: 21 to 21
 The dissenting judge frames his reasoning in equally self-referential terms, stating that he is "not convinced that Proposition 8 lacks a rational relationship to legitimate state interests." (1673). Here, the keyword "legitimate" is modified by equally unhelpful "state interests." The primary issue supporters of Proposition 8 identified as a "state interest" was that of procreation and childrearing. It's hard for me to see what about this topic is inherently part of a state's interest; the kinds of arguments that justify such a connection seem to me to justify almost any activity as a matter of "state interest." In any case, there is no extra-legal practical definition of "state interests," it is again a legal conclusion reached by courts when courts think it should be reached.
Changed:
<
<
The dissent here mentions the "rational basis" test, the default level of scrutiny employed by courts in due process and equal protection cases. This raises another host of transcendental nonsense concerns. The first is the decision to apply rational basis review, rather than intermediate or strict scrutiny. "Proposition 8 is a classification neither involving fundamental rights nor proceeding along suspect lines . . . [so] I do not address the application of strict scrutiny review." (1651). Why isn't marriage a fundamental right, despite the fact that the Supreme Court stated that "[m]arriage is one of the basic civil rights of man, fundamental to our very existence and survival" while striking down anti-miscegenation statutes? Loving v. Virginia, 87 S.Ct. 1817, 1824 (1967). Because the judge here says so. A suspect class is loosely defined as a minority group which has been purposefully discriminated against because of an immutable characteristic (religion is included, raising questions about the definition of immutability). Why are homosexuals not a suspect class? Because the judge here says so.
>
>
Is the goal in these two grafs to forget any Fourteenth Amendment law you know, to avoid learning any, or to indicate that it is transcendental nonsense so that it doesn't matter whether you learn it or forget it?

The dissent here mentions the "rational basis" test, the default level of scrutiny employed by courts in due process and equal protection cases. This raises another host of transcendental nonsense concerns. The first is the decision to apply rational basis review, rather than intermediate or strict scrutiny. "Proposition 8 is a classification neither involving fundamental rights nor proceeding along suspect lines . . . [so] I do not address the application of strict scrutiny review." (1651). Why isn't marriage a fundamental right, despite the fact that the Supreme Court stated that "[m]arriage is one of the basic civil rights of man, fundamental to our very existence and survival" while striking down anti-miscegenation statutes? Loving v. Virginia, 87 S.Ct. 1817, 1824 (1967).

Why cite the case to the unofficial reporter? Because Westlaw prefers to take you away from the US Reports? Why don't you link directly to the opinion online, so people can read it? Did you? It would have answered the rhetorical question you asked, and given you some further basis to understand the legal analysis in the case you are supposedly trying to grasp.

Because the judge here says so. A suspect class is loosely defined as a minority group which has been purposefully discriminated against because of an immutable characteristic (religion is included, raising questions about the definition of immutability). Why are homosexuals not a suspect class? Because the judge here says so.

Perhaps because the Supreme Court has not said so? You have neither reviewed the law concerning the definition of suspect classes nor explained why the Court of Appeals, well aware that the Supreme Court has declined repeated opportunities to rule on the question, should have done so.
 Even if the decision to choose "rational basis" review could be defended in real-world terms, we would not have advanced very far in our battle against transcendental nonsense. We would have to investigate more legal conclusions: whether or not Proposition 8 was "reasonably" related to, again, a "legitimate state interest."
Added:
>
>
Given that "marriage" itself is transcendental nonsense in the same sense you're using it here, what battle against transcendental nonsense could we be fighting? If you're really going to apply the approach you seem to think you're endorsing here, the case isn't about anything and doesn't have any meaning no matter which way it comes out.
 

Words are what they do

Line: 33 to 66
 I was reminded of the discussion regarding the PPACA and whether there is a meaningful difference between calling something a "penalty" or a "tax." In Perry v. Brown, even the majority recognized that those with "domestic partnerships" in California were entitled to "rights and responsibilities that are identical to those of married spouses . . . ." (1610). At first glance, this may seem like an analogy for the penalty/tax argument, a matter of mere semantics. However, the word "marriage" has a unique place in our society, and the majority included a 300-word paragraph detailing this fact (page 1613). You can read a short blog post that includes the relevant paragraph here.
Added:
>
>
If you need the quotation, why not point at it in the opinion? If you don't need it, why are you sending your reader to some random person's blog? Why did you need to cite another complex case you're going to discuss in order not to discuss the reasoning about why "marriage" isn't transcendental nonsense within the borders of an opinion you're dismissing on that ground anyway?
 Similarly, the supporters of Proposition 8 argued that there was no difference between the rights of homosexuals before In re Marriage Cases, 43 Cal.4th 757 (Cal 2008) and after Proposition 8 passed. Only in the intervening six month period were homosexuals able to marry in California. Not even the majority claims that states are constitutionally required to extend marriage to homosexual couples, and the supporters of Prop 8 argue that there is no difference between not extending the right to marry and revoking the right to marry. Just as the majority argued above that there is unique symbolism to the word "marriage," here they argued that there is symbolic importance to the act of revoking the right to marry. I agree that a state’s active revocation of a certain group’s rights puts an official stamp on discrimination.
Added:
>
>
In which case, why not go further and argue that doing so creates a suspect class where there was none before? See my brief with Pam Karlan in Romer v. Evans.
 

Judges are people, too

Line: 45 to 89
 -- By MarcLegrand - 13 Feb 2012
Deleted:
<
<
Good job. This might be interesting: http://www.slate.com/articles/news_and_politics/jurisprudence/2012/02/why_the_proponents_of_a_gay_marriage_ban_will_soon_be_speechless.html
 \ No newline at end of file
Added:
>
>
I don't understand this draft. The use of Cohen seems to be primarily to make it unnecessary to understand the law you're trying to learn something about. You don't make it easier for the reader to understand the case, you distract yourself into making some minor errors or omissions of your own, and when it's over we don't seem to know anything about what happened that we didn't know before.

Why not try another draft that presents an idea of yours about the opinions, and which also involves actually explaining what legal issues the court thinks it's deciding and how it decides them?


MarcLegrandFirstPaper 2 - 14 Feb 2012 - Main.DavidHirsch
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="FirstPaper"
Line: 44 to 44
 Publication or not, we know that the majority was written by Judge Reinhardt and Judge Hawkins, nominated by Jimmy Carter and Bill Clinton, respectively. Judge Smith, who dissented, was nominated by George W. Bush. "According to the classical theory, these things have nothing to do with the way courts decide cases." (Cohen, 846). Even in a functionalist model, such facts are not necessarily determinative. After all, Proposition 8 was first struck down in district court by Judge Walker, who was originally nominated by Ronald Reagan and then re-nominated by George H. W. Bush. Still, the fact that the opinion in Perry v. Brown is basically premised on self-referential legal conclusions makes me wonder what role human biases played in the determination of those conclusions.

-- By MarcLegrand - 13 Feb 2012

Added:
>
>
Good job. This might be interesting: http://www.slate.com/articles/news_and_politics/jurisprudence/2012/02/why_the_proponents_of_a_gay_marriage_ban_will_soon_be_speechless.html
 \ No newline at end of file

MarcLegrandFirstPaper 1 - 13 Feb 2012 - Main.MarcLegrand
Line: 1 to 1
Added:
>
>
META TOPICPARENT name="FirstPaper"

Perry v. Brown v. Cohen

Introduction

I wanted to write about the recently-decided Ninth Circuit opinion in Perry v. Brown, and I thought it might be interesting (at least for me) to try to apply a few of the ideas from Felix Cohen’s Transcendental Nonsense.

Legal Concepts

"Legal concepts … are supernatural entities which do not have a verifiably existence except to the eyes of faith." (Cohen, 821).

The Perry majority frames the question they have been asked to decide as follows:

"[Did] the People of California have legitimate reasons for enacting a constitutional amendment that serves only to take away from same-sex couples the right to have their lifelong relationships dignified by the official status of 'marriage,' and to compel the State ...to substitute the label of 'domestic partnership' for their relationships?" (1615).

In this framing, the crucial word seems to be "legitimate." When Cohen describes a court's approach to determining "actual value," he points out that "[t]he actual value of a utility's property, then, is a function of the court's decision, and the court's decision cannot be based in fact upon the actual value of the property." (Cohen, 818). The idea of "legitimacy" in Perry v. Brown is a similarly circular legal conclusion; whether or not there was a legitimate reason for enacting Proposition 8 is a function of whether or not the court finds that there was.

The dissenting judge frames his reasoning in equally self-referential terms, stating that he is "not convinced that Proposition 8 lacks a rational relationship to legitimate state interests." (1673). Here, the keyword "legitimate" is modified by equally unhelpful "state interests." The primary issue supporters of Proposition 8 identified as a "state interest" was that of procreation and childrearing. It's hard for me to see what about this topic is inherently part of a state's interest; the kinds of arguments that justify such a connection seem to me to justify almost any activity as a matter of "state interest." In any case, there is no extra-legal practical definition of "state interests," it is again a legal conclusion reached by courts when courts think it should be reached.

The dissent here mentions the "rational basis" test, the default level of scrutiny employed by courts in due process and equal protection cases. This raises another host of transcendental nonsense concerns. The first is the decision to apply rational basis review, rather than intermediate or strict scrutiny. "Proposition 8 is a classification neither involving fundamental rights nor proceeding along suspect lines . . . [so] I do not address the application of strict scrutiny review." (1651). Why isn't marriage a fundamental right, despite the fact that the Supreme Court stated that "[m]arriage is one of the basic civil rights of man, fundamental to our very existence and survival" while striking down anti-miscegenation statutes? Loving v. Virginia, 87 S.Ct. 1817, 1824 (1967). Because the judge here says so. A suspect class is loosely defined as a minority group which has been purposefully discriminated against because of an immutable characteristic (religion is included, raising questions about the definition of immutability). Why are homosexuals not a suspect class? Because the judge here says so.

Even if the decision to choose "rational basis" review could be defended in real-world terms, we would not have advanced very far in our battle against transcendental nonsense. We would have to investigate more legal conclusions: whether or not Proposition 8 was "reasonably" related to, again, a "legitimate state interest."

Words are what they do

"[T]he meaning of a definition is found in its consequences." (Cohen, 838).

I was reminded of the discussion regarding the PPACA and whether there is a meaningful difference between calling something a "penalty" or a "tax." In Perry v. Brown, even the majority recognized that those with "domestic partnerships" in California were entitled to "rights and responsibilities that are identical to those of married spouses . . . ." (1610). At first glance, this may seem like an analogy for the penalty/tax argument, a matter of mere semantics. However, the word "marriage" has a unique place in our society, and the majority included a 300-word paragraph detailing this fact (page 1613). You can read a short blog post that includes the relevant paragraph here.

Similarly, the supporters of Proposition 8 argued that there was no difference between the rights of homosexuals before In re Marriage Cases, 43 Cal.4th 757 (Cal 2008) and after Proposition 8 passed. Only in the intervening six month period were homosexuals able to marry in California. Not even the majority claims that states are constitutionally required to extend marriage to homosexual couples, and the supporters of Prop 8 argue that there is no difference between not extending the right to marry and revoking the right to marry. Just as the majority argued above that there is unique symbolism to the word "marriage," here they argued that there is symbolic importance to the act of revoking the right to marry. I agree that a state’s active revocation of a certain group’s rights puts an official stamp on discrimination.

Judges are people, too

"There is at present no publication showing the political, economic, and professional background and activities of our various judges." (Cohen, 846)

Publication or not, we know that the majority was written by Judge Reinhardt and Judge Hawkins, nominated by Jimmy Carter and Bill Clinton, respectively. Judge Smith, who dissented, was nominated by George W. Bush. "According to the classical theory, these things have nothing to do with the way courts decide cases." (Cohen, 846). Even in a functionalist model, such facts are not necessarily determinative. After all, Proposition 8 was first struck down in district court by Judge Walker, who was originally nominated by Ronald Reagan and then re-nominated by George H. W. Bush. Still, the fact that the opinion in Perry v. Brown is basically premised on self-referential legal conclusions makes me wonder what role human biases played in the determination of those conclusions.

-- By MarcLegrand - 13 Feb 2012


Revision 4r4 - 29 Apr 2012 - 01:37:01 - MarcLegrand
Revision 3r3 - 15 Apr 2012 - 20:00:46 - EbenMoglen
Revision 2r2 - 14 Feb 2012 - 00:26:05 - DavidHirsch
Revision 1r1 - 13 Feb 2012 - 03:03:08 - MarcLegrand
This site is powered by the TWiki collaboration platform.
All material on this collaboration platform is the property of the contributing authors.
All material marked as authored by Eben Moglen is available under the license terms CC-BY-SA version 4.
Syndicate this site RSSATOM