Law in the Internet Society

View   r3  >  r2  >  r1
TWikiGuestSecondEssay 3 - 22 Nov 2023 - Main.LudovicoColetti
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="SecondEssay"
Deleted:
<
<
-- NinniSusanThomas The Right Against Self-Incrimination in the Digital Age
 
Deleted:
<
<
Mobile phones almost being an extension of our lives, with it tracking every conversation, expenditure, location, can act as the pivotal part if one was to be involved in a criminal investigation. The question of whether a person can be forced to hand over passcodes of their electronic devices that could lead to self-incriminating information has been discussed in recent times in both the United States and India. It raises very interesting questions surrounding the right against self-incrimination and the right to privacy.
 
Changed:
<
<
Current scenario in the United States
>
>

*Intellectual Property and Incentives to Innovation: does it really work?*

 
Deleted:
<
<
In the United States, relying on the foregone conclusion doctrine (Fisher v. United States), it may be argued that as the contents of the phones of accused would already be known to the investigating authorities, forcing them to give passwords of their phones cannot be seen as a violation of their right against self-incrimination. This question of law, wherein the extension of the right under the Fifth Amendment to not provide a phone’s password is pending in an appeal to the Supreme Court in Andrews v. New Jersey. There have been divergent views in multiple State Supreme Courts as well.
 
Changed:
<
<
Context in India and current situation
>
>
Intellectual property rights have long been regarded as crucial incentives for innovation, providing creators and inventors with the protection and recognition they need to thrive in a competitive market. The traditional view is that giving a (limited in time) monopoly over an idea is the best way to reward those who came up with it, and that without the monopoly nobody would try to innovate.
 
Changed:
<
<
Article 20(3) of the Constitution of India guarantees the right against self-incrimination. Over the years, the Indian Supreme Court’s judgments have provided different - and even conflicting - rationales for this right. These justifications can be broadly grouped into two categories: crime-control justifications and due process justifications. Crime-control justifications view the right against self-incrimination as instrumental towards the criminal law’s goal of uncovering the truth and punishing the guilty. According to this justification, forcing people to incriminate themselves will, more often than not, yield false testimony and lead criminal investigations astray. Due process justifications, on the other hand, view the right against self-incrimination to be part of a broader panoply of criminal procedure safeguards aimed at preserving the dignity of the individual, and maintaining a balance of power between the individual and the State.
>
>
This is confirmed by Institutions such as the European Commission: “the primary function of intellectual property rights is to protect and stimulate the development and distribution of new products and the provision of new services”. But the fact that the IP monopoly actually promotes creativity should not be accepted uncritically. In fact, criticisms exist and are expressed from a historical and economical point of view in the book “Against Intellectual Monopoly” by Professors Michele Boldrin and David Levine.
 
Deleted:
<
<
The Indian Supreme Court has gone back and forth between these two justifications. The exact text of Article 20(3) reads: “no person accused of an offence shall be compelled to be a witness against himself.” In Kathi Kalu Oghad, the Supreme Court considered the question of whether compulsory taking of fingerprints and handwriting samples were hit by the bar against self-incrimination. The Court held that they were not. What weighed with the Court, among other things, was that fingerprints (and, to a lesser extent, handwriting samples) could not be altered by an individual at will. Consequently, whether or not these samples were coerced from an individual, their intrinsic qualities would remain unchanged. It can be clearly seen that this reasoning fits well within the crime-control justification: linking the right against self-incrimination to an individual’s ability (or lack thereof) to alter a piece of evidence directly flows from a primary concern about the goal of criminal law being to determine truth and punish the guilty.
 
Changed:
<
<
On the other hand, in Selvi v State, the Supreme Court held that the compulsory taking of a lie-detector test, brain mapping (HEAP) test, and narco-analysis - all interrogation techniques - were all unconstitutional. In the course of its analysis, the Court did not ask about the alterability or mutability of the evidence (a brain scan, for example, would fall well within the unalterability paradigm), but focused instead on the right to mental privacy, and read Article 20(3) along with Article 21 (right to life and personal liberty) of the Indian Constitution.
>
>

Inventions and Patents

 
Deleted:
<
<
There is thus a tension in Indian jurisprudence between the crime control and due process justifications of the right against self-incrimination. Whether the right, thus, protects data recovered from an individual’s personal mobile phone, or other device, in the course of investigation, depends on which of these justifications is held to be the correct understanding of Article 20(3). Under the due process justification, a person should be entitled to refuse to provide their password to the police during the investigation. Under the crime control justification, on the other hand, this refusal will be more difficult to defend.
 
Changed:
<
<
Conclusion
>
>
The authors retrace the history of the technological development of our society in the last two centuries – starting with Watt’s steam engine - highlighting how often new ideas come up by chance while the inventor is working on something else, and the patent is obtained at a later stage to limit competition.
 
Changed:
<
<
The questions of whether forcing a person to provide their password or a fingerprint to allow investigating authorities to access their electronic devices is akin to being forced to give their DNA or undergo polygraph testing, which is clearly a violation of their privacy, will have to be debated further in both these jurisdictions.
>
>
In the case of Watt, the authors observe how during the validity of his steam engine patent (granted in 1769) nothing much happened in terms of development in England’s steam engine capability. During that period, Watt’s energies were mostly devoted to preventing competitors from copying his engine. He also went after inventors who had developed better products, such as the “Hornblower” engine. Eventually, after the expiry of his patents, the production and efficiency of steam engines skyrocketed, driven by improvements that were kept off the market until then, like the Hornblower engine. What’s worth noting is that (i) Watt was limited by the rush to patents he himself had started, as further improvements he came up with were prevented by another inventor’s patent; (ii) the expiry did not hurt Watt’s business, instead he started selling more engines and could raise prices; and (iii) in 1812 a new improvement, the “Cornish” engine, was invented but not patented. This was followed by a rise of coal-efficiency by a factor of five, whereas coal-efficiency had remained unchanged during Watt’s monopoly.
 
Added:
>
>
The retardation of innovation and economic growth due to monopolies on the various versions of steam engines is an example of what the authors call the “IP inefficiency”. The argument that patents foster innovation is also not supported by numbers. In the 1990s there was an extraordinary increase in the number of new patents registered in the United States and Europe. However, this increase was not accompanied by a proportionate increase in the index that is used as common measure of technological improvement, the Total Factor Productivity (TFP).
 
Added:
>
>

Creativity and Copyright

 
Added:
>
>
Copyright gives an astonishingly long monopoly over the production of copies of an idea: 70 years after the death of the author. Traditionally, we justify this by asking: ‘Without copyright, how would an author get paid?’.
 
Changed:
<
<
 
<--/commentPlugin-->
>
>
However, artistic works have been created throughout history also in the absence of any kind of monopolistic protection. Copyright originated first as a form of censorship and then as a tax instrument. Only towards the end of the 19th Century it became the cornerstone of the business strategy of publishing houses in America and Europe. Since then, the life of copyright has been progressively extended, with any extension benefiting mostly the media companies rather than the artist (who is dead when copyright expires). The extension of the monopoly period does not seem to have produced an increase or improvement in artistic production.

Software

The inconsistency within the doctrine asserting that intellectual property fosters innovation becomes glaringly evident when examining the realm of information technology and software. In the context of information technology, the rapid pace of advancement and the collaborative nature of software development stand in contrast to the traditional model of intellectual property. Boldrin & Levine argue that most of the innovation in this industry – including the internet – took place without the protection of intellectual property.

Patent protection was extended to computers programs by the Supreme Court 1981 decision in Diamond v. Dier. Therefore, each of the inventions made in the field before that case did not benefit from patent protection. In addition, before the rise of Microsoft copyright played a little role in the software industry.

The best evidence that copyright and patents are not needed to make better software is the existence of the free software movement, pioneered by Richard Stallman. Open-source software is released under licenses that allow copying and modifying to the extent that the new software is released under the same license. Many flourishing companies and highly paid programmers voluntarily choose to develop open-source software, like in the case of RedHat? , the market leader of Linux-based software products, and Canonical, the producer of Ubuntu.

Conclusion

A closer examination reveals that the idea that intellectual property is the best way to increase innovation and creation by rewarding inventors/creators is based on a misconception. On one hand, creators would still be incentivized to create in the absence of IP right; on the other hand, the monopoly over ideas creates social costs, as it’s widely recognized for any kind of monopoly.

IP rights are recognized by the US Constitution “To promote the progress of science and useful arts, by securing for limited times to authors and inventors the exclusive right to their respective writings and discoveries”. However, as noted by Stallman, the bargain that currently exists between the rights of the authors and those of the public is not the only possible bargain. Better bargain might be found by reducing copyright privileges in stages, in terms of duration over time or extent of the fair use.

 \ No newline at end of file

TWikiGuestSecondEssay 2 - 18 Dec 2021 - Main.NinniSusanThomas
Line: 1 to 1
Changed:
<
<
META TOPICPARENT name="WebPreferences"
>
>
META TOPICPARENT name="SecondEssay"
 -- NinniSusanThomas The Right Against Self-Incrimination in the Digital Age

TWikiGuestSecondEssay 1 - 17 Dec 2021 - Main.NinniSusanThomas
Line: 1 to 1
Added:
>
>
META TOPICPARENT name="WebPreferences"

-- NinniSusanThomas The Right Against Self-Incrimination in the Digital Age

Mobile phones almost being an extension of our lives, with it tracking every conversation, expenditure, location, can act as the pivotal part if one was to be involved in a criminal investigation. The question of whether a person can be forced to hand over passcodes of their electronic devices that could lead to self-incriminating information has been discussed in recent times in both the United States and India. It raises very interesting questions surrounding the right against self-incrimination and the right to privacy.

Current scenario in the United States

In the United States, relying on the foregone conclusion doctrine (Fisher v. United States), it may be argued that as the contents of the phones of accused would already be known to the investigating authorities, forcing them to give passwords of their phones cannot be seen as a violation of their right against self-incrimination. This question of law, wherein the extension of the right under the Fifth Amendment to not provide a phone’s password is pending in an appeal to the Supreme Court in Andrews v. New Jersey. There have been divergent views in multiple State Supreme Courts as well.

Context in India and current situation

Article 20(3) of the Constitution of India guarantees the right against self-incrimination. Over the years, the Indian Supreme Court’s judgments have provided different - and even conflicting - rationales for this right. These justifications can be broadly grouped into two categories: crime-control justifications and due process justifications. Crime-control justifications view the right against self-incrimination as instrumental towards the criminal law’s goal of uncovering the truth and punishing the guilty. According to this justification, forcing people to incriminate themselves will, more often than not, yield false testimony and lead criminal investigations astray. Due process justifications, on the other hand, view the right against self-incrimination to be part of a broader panoply of criminal procedure safeguards aimed at preserving the dignity of the individual, and maintaining a balance of power between the individual and the State.

The Indian Supreme Court has gone back and forth between these two justifications. The exact text of Article 20(3) reads: “no person accused of an offence shall be compelled to be a witness against himself.” In Kathi Kalu Oghad, the Supreme Court considered the question of whether compulsory taking of fingerprints and handwriting samples were hit by the bar against self-incrimination. The Court held that they were not. What weighed with the Court, among other things, was that fingerprints (and, to a lesser extent, handwriting samples) could not be altered by an individual at will. Consequently, whether or not these samples were coerced from an individual, their intrinsic qualities would remain unchanged. It can be clearly seen that this reasoning fits well within the crime-control justification: linking the right against self-incrimination to an individual’s ability (or lack thereof) to alter a piece of evidence directly flows from a primary concern about the goal of criminal law being to determine truth and punish the guilty.

On the other hand, in Selvi v State, the Supreme Court held that the compulsory taking of a lie-detector test, brain mapping (HEAP) test, and narco-analysis - all interrogation techniques - were all unconstitutional. In the course of its analysis, the Court did not ask about the alterability or mutability of the evidence (a brain scan, for example, would fall well within the unalterability paradigm), but focused instead on the right to mental privacy, and read Article 20(3) along with Article 21 (right to life and personal liberty) of the Indian Constitution.

There is thus a tension in Indian jurisprudence between the crime control and due process justifications of the right against self-incrimination. Whether the right, thus, protects data recovered from an individual’s personal mobile phone, or other device, in the course of investigation, depends on which of these justifications is held to be the correct understanding of Article 20(3). Under the due process justification, a person should be entitled to refuse to provide their password to the police during the investigation. Under the crime control justification, on the other hand, this refusal will be more difficult to defend.

Conclusion

The questions of whether forcing a person to provide their password or a fingerprint to allow investigating authorities to access their electronic devices is akin to being forced to give their DNA or undergo polygraph testing, which is clearly a violation of their privacy, will have to be debated further in both these jurisdictions.

 
<--/commentPlugin-->

Revision 3r3 - 22 Nov 2023 - 22:54:06 - LudovicoColetti
Revision 2r2 - 18 Dec 2021 - 17:38:10 - NinniSusanThomas
Revision 1r1 - 17 Dec 2021 - 04:04:36 - NinniSusanThomas
This site is powered by the TWiki collaboration platform.
All material on this collaboration platform is the property of the contributing authors.
All material marked as authored by Eben Moglen is available under the license terms CC-BY-SA version 4.
Syndicate this site RSSATOM