| |
EdwardBontkowskiSecondPaper 3 - 02 Nov 2010 - Main.EbenMoglen
|
|
META TOPICPARENT | name="SecondPaper%25" |
| |
< < | READY FOR REVIEW | | Reasonability and Expectations of Internet Privacy
-- By EdwardBontkowski - 03 May 2010 | | Conclusion
In my opinion, the reliance on the idea of an individual assuming the risk attempts too narrowly to pin down a specific interpretation of what should be considered reasonable. The pervasiveness of the internet into all aspects of society and the nature of the way resources are divided make it increasingly convenient and expected to store personal information of some kind or another on a third party network. Society defines what is “reasonable” for a person to assume, and the increasing frequency with which Facebook, Gmail, and other website’s security protocols are debated in a public forum make it at least plausible that there are many people who believe “internet privacy” should not be an oxymoron. | |
> > |
One of the reasons I make an effort in my teaching to provide clear,
explicit historical context connecting the formative tradition of our
constitutional law with the current issues is to avoid the confusion
that arises from the attempt (which is never not being tried by
somebody, despite its disutility) to invent "constitutional law" as a
subject divorced from the contingencies of historical development.
The contour of the Fourth Amendment is poorly captured in a short
string of a few decades' cases in which "reasonable expectation of
privacy" is used as a synonym for "reasonable." The facts that the
Amendment's language protects places, and things in those places,
that it concerns a right of security, not a right of privacy, and
that its language grows out of controversies involving political
offenses are all part of the historical context of the limitation on
state power. Reasoning as though the Fourth Amendment were equal
to a provision calling for reasonable privacy expectations to be
protected against searches by government agents unless a warrant has
issued upon showing of probable cause to a neutral magistrate will
not correctly predict the outcomes of the cases over any lengthy
period of time, and will certainly not explain how the people who
expressed this principle in eighteenth-century British North American
legal documents understood it.
The sharp distinction between criminal and other coercive
governmental process is also ahistorical. The common law is not
quite so sharp as that, for one thing. To forget, moreover, how
important political offenses are in English legal history with
respect to the rights of criminal defendants generally, is both to
misunderstand the past and to be a little complacent about our
present. We certainly do like to think of our criminal law system
as free of political offense prosecutions. But this is not quite as
simple as it tends to seem to us. In the precise context of the
Fourth Amendment's development out of English historical
circumstances, as I labored to demonstrate in class, the political
offenses of the seventeenth century, and the use of mixed civil and
criminal modes of coercion against political dissidents, both played
a significant role.
One could have a sort of purely prescriptive constitutional reasoning
which was not at all about how words came to be used or what they
meant to the people who used them, but was only responsive to current
concerns. I have more sympathy for that approach than most
constitutional law professors, because they mostly (quite correctly)
think this would result in a constitutional law indistinguishable
from politics, which they—being constitutional law
professors—think is not the case with the constitutional law
they teach. But even I find it difficult to take very seriously an
argument that asks me explicitly to ignore the history of our
constitutional arrangements in order to make constitutional policy
based on purely logical relationships among secondary entities, like
the phraseology of judicial opinions or the strength of our
contemporary confidence in the political independence and
self-restraint of our prosecutors, police, and internal security
organs. A Fourth Amendment that protects privacy interests in my
information held in third hands would be a useful provision in a
constitution, but it isn't what is in this constitution, unless this
constitution is whatever we happen to say it is today.
| |
You are entitled to restrict access to your paper if you want to. But we all derive immense benefit from reading one another's work, and I hope you won't feel the need unless the subject matter is personal and its disclosure would be harmful or undesirable.
To restrict access to your paper simply delete the "#" on the next line: |
|
|
|
This site is powered by the TWiki collaboration platform. All material on this collaboration platform is the property of the contributing authors. All material marked as authored by Eben Moglen is available under the license terms CC-BY-SA version 4.
|
|
| |